AUB ScholarWorks

Wider reflective equilibrium -

Show simple item record

dc.contributor.author Youness, Mahmoud Riad,
dc.date.accessioned 2017-12-12T07:59:29Z
dc.date.available 2017-12-12T07:59:29Z
dc.date.copyright 2019-12
dc.date.issued 2016
dc.date.submitted 2016
dc.identifier.other b19030587
dc.identifier.uri http://hdl.handle.net/10938/21014
dc.description Thesis. M.A. American University of Beirut. Department of Philosophy, 2016. T:6526
dc.description Advisor : Dr. Bashshar Haidar, Professor, Philosophy ; Members of Committee : Dr. Bana Bashour, Associate Professor, Philosophy ; Dr. Ray Brassier, Professor, Philososphy.
dc.description Includes bibliographical references (leaves 114-124)
dc.description.abstract The debate over moral intuitions has a distinguished pedigree. We are far, however, from 19th and early 20th century intuitionism(s) whereby a presumed intuitive faculty is said to have direct access to moral truth. What contemporary moral philosophers grant intuitions is no more than initial credibility, and that for want of better starting points. These philosophers disagree as to how to proceed once we acquire our presumptively credible intuitions – usually through thought experiments. A prominent suggestion, insofar as method is concerned, is to treat moral intuitions as data, and to strive, a là natural sciences, to arrive at a theory that makes them cohere. Principles are devised that give system to the relevant intuitions, and the lack of coherence forces revisions of both intuitions and principles. The said method was articulated and furthered by John Rawls who dubbed it wide reflective equilibrium. Not all philosophers, however, are satisfied with intuitions. Many argue that they are not credible, not even initially, as they are (inter- and intra-personally) unstable, culturally variable, and subject to emotional manipulation. Wide reflective equilibrium, as such, is no longer tenable a method, nor thought experiments a device. The different arguments against intuitions, however, derive sustenance from the fact that people’s intuitions are not on a par. Understanding intuitions as externalizations of the agent’s epistemically-relevant dispositions explains the discrepancy in reported intuitions, and admits it as a fact to reckon with. Intuitive differences are then taken into consideration in defending reflective equilibrium, and, subsequently, modifying it by (re-)establishing the centrality of moral psychology in moral method, and the inevitability of expert intuitions – hence wider reflective equilibrium.
dc.format.extent 1 online resource (viii, 124 leaves)
dc.language.iso eng
dc.relation.ispartof Theses, Dissertations, and Projects
dc.subject.classification T:006526
dc.subject.lcsh Rawls, John, 1921-2002.
dc.subject.lcsh Justification (Ethics)
dc.subject.lcsh Intuition -- Philosophy.
dc.subject.lcsh Ethics.
dc.title Wider reflective equilibrium -
dc.type Thesis
dc.contributor.department Faculty of Arts and Sciences.
dc.contributor.department Department of Philosophy,
dc.contributor.institution American University of Beirut.


Files in this item

This item appears in the following Collection(s)

Show simple item record

Search AUB ScholarWorks


Browse

My Account